Site icon Jotted Lines

How was the shift from behaviourism to cognitive psychology ‘revolutionary’ in the Kuhnian sense?

The advent of cognitive science at the centre of studying psychology is widely portrayed to be a revolutionary event.  It was in the 1950s that the shift from behaviourism to cognitive psychology took its first bold step.  There has been no reverting back to behaviourism as the dominant paradigm within psychology ever since. Cognitive psychology is one of the disciplines in psychology that focuses on studying internal mental processes.  How individuals perceive, conceive, recall from memory, articulate their views and arrive at conclusions, etc, are studied. As opposed to Behavioural psychology, Cognitive psychology adopts a scientific analytic method rather than introspective or speculative theorizing.  At the outset, it acknowledges the presence of such internal mental states as knowledge, belief, motivation, desire, etc. This essay will evaluate how ‘revolutionary’ an event, in the Kuhnian sense, was the placement of cognitive science at the centre of psychology.

Before Cognitive Psychology attained recognition Behaviourism was the dominant school of thought.  Intellectuals such as Noam Chomsky and Alfred Adler have contributed enormously to the later development of this school, by way of its critical reprisal.  Under Behaviourism, much of human agency is thought of as a product of conditioned responses, where, rewards are used to reinforce desirable behaviour and punishments used to deter unwanted behaviour.  Chomsky, in particular, challenged these assumptions and offered a radically new model of mental development that draws on the innate and intrinsic human potentialities as opposed to learned behaviour. (Neisser, 1997, p.44)  While behaviourism’s relevance for studying psychology has diminished, it’s utility to other disciplines within humanities remains.  Proponents of behaviourism believe that, even within psychology, it has made significant contributions.  Hence, it is fair to assume that the cognitive revolution is not an undisputed fact.

Thomas Kuhn was one of the intellectuals who took issue with the orthodox view of scientific progress.  The orthodoxy proclaimed that scientific knowledge develops incrementally, by way of accretion.  In this view, “new knowledge does not supplant the old, but rather, new discoveries are added to the extant ‘stockpile that constitutes scientific technique and knowledge’”. (O’Donohue & Ferguson, 2003, p.87) Kuhn took objection to this view and cited the examples of Copernicus, Lavoisier, Newton, Plank, Einstein, Darwin, etc.  He showed how, rather than merely ‘adding’ to existing knowledge, their theories and concepts radically altered conventional wisdom. Such a radical change is both the cause and effect of the ‘Gestalt switch’ in which these scientists perceived basic phenomena in a fundamentally different manner.  While revolution in scientific progress in thus backed up by empirical evidence, it still does not lead to the conclusion that cognitive psychology is one such.

Kuhn had written at length on the subject of scientific revolutions in his seminal 1960 work The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.  Going by this understanding, the behavioural paradigm “was not shown to have ‘drowned in a sea of anamolies’, and was not usurped by the cognitive paradigm with a problem-solving exemplar better able to accommodate those anamolies.” (O’Donohue & Ferguson, 2003, p.85)  Kuhn thus makes it clear that the perceived shift to the new paradigm is not a natural course of scientific evolution.  The debate on whether the cognitive revolution actually occurred should be informed by this key observation of Kuhn’s.

It is easy to get carried away by the hype and popularity surrounding cognitive psychology.  It is true that citations in scholarly journals underscore the ascendency of cognitive psychology.  Such statistics also reveal how behavioural psychology is no longer the buzz within the scientific community.  But one cannot take such trends as proofs for a bona fide scientific revolution.  The trend merely illustrates “a sociological phenomenon – a change in allegiance, that, interestingly, may be due in part to the claim (which has immense rhetorical value) that a scientific revolution has indeed taken place.” (O’Donohue & Ferguson, 2003, p.86) That the Cognitive Revolution was a contested idea is learnt from numerous scholarly critiques the idea has drawn.  For example, influential scholars such as Popper, Lakatos, Laudan and Gross have articulated their doubts about the verity of the revolution.  To illustrate, one strong reason why one should be cautious in the acceptance of cognitive revolution is its implications for older disciplines within science. For example, the centuries old treatment of mind and consciousness is contested in cognitive science. The

“contents of conscious experience, with their subjective qualities, long banned as being mere acausal epiphenomena or as just identical to brain activity or otherwise in conflict with the laws of the conservation of energy, have now made a dramatic comeback. Reconceived in the new outlook, subjective mental states become functionally interactive and essential for a full explanation of conscious behaviour.” (Sperry, 1993, p.879)

Science’s constant pursuit of knowledge and truth leads to a quandary, whereby all scientific inquiry is directed toward gaining understanding of a few fundamental questions relating to the universe and human consciousness. If scientists are unable to unlock these basic secrets of our world, then science might soon hit a stumbling block around which it cannot get around. Those who are critical of the utility of scientific inquiry point out, that, even ascertaining answers to these fundamental questions might quench our curiosity but might prove of little practical utility.  So, either scenario suggests an End of Science. On the other hand, people like Thomas Kuhn and Derek de Solla Price, celebrate the possibilities of science and its centrality to understanding limits of human knowledge and experience.  They emphasize that instead of a linear-progressive model, scientific inquiry can just as well undertake a paradigm shift toward achieving more dynamism.  They foresee “the capacity of human imagination and its potential-not just in pushing the limits of science.” (Bauer, 1997) But evidence is lacking to substantiate this quantum leap in the field of psychology.

Another problem with assigning the tag of revolution to cognitive psychology is its relation to preceding paradigms.  In other words, cognitive psychology did not spring out of a lacuna within the academic discipline.  To the contrary, upon its emergence, it competed for space with the already established behavioural psychology.  In this sense, cognitive psychology is a ‘counter-revolution’ and does not fully fit the description of Kuhn’s.  There is also a lack of consensus over the adequacy of the term ‘revolution’, for there were no “cataclysmic events, leaders, or radicalisms” attached to the cognitive movement. (Watrin & Darwich, 2012, p.273)   Mandler hits the nail on the head when he states that

“the well-documented cognitive ‘revolution’ was, to a large extent, an evolving return to attitudes and trends that were present before the advent of behaviourism and that were alive and well outside of the United States, where behaviourism had not developed any coherent support” (Watrin & Darwich, 2012, p.273)

Such being the case, cognitive psychology was not only not a revolution, but more accurately it was a reactionary movement.  However, if cognitive psychology could not be granted the status of a revolution on Kuhn’s scientific paradigmatic terms, there were other academic currents that give credence to the claim.  For example, by the 1950s, it had become clear that behaviourism as the basis of psychology cannot succeed. As Noam Chomsky noted, “defining psychology as the science of behaviour was like defining physics as the science of meter reading. If scientific psychology were to succeed, mentalistic concepts would have to integrate and explain the behavioural data.” (Miller, 2003, p.142)  Hence a vacuum was created within psychology to find a new conceptual framework.  It was this void that cognitive science offered to fulfil.  Although ‘mind’ had never really disappeared from social or clinical psychology, its relevance was losing ground especially in the United States.  Hence the revival of the centrality of ‘mentalism’ to psychology is a testament to the strong overhaul awaiting the discipline.  Disillusioned by B. F. Skinner’s rather rigid behaviourism and the somewhat obtuse psychophysics of S.S. Stevens, people like Miller, Chomsky, O’Donohue, Goodman, etc turned to social psychology.  This was an important turn of events, for it formally created the Centre for Cognitive Studies at Harvard. (White, 1999, p.197) The participation of the Carnegie Corporation of New York added prestige to the fledgling scientific movement. There were similar developments across the Atlantic at the Cambridge University, where, Sir Frederic Bartlett’s work on memory and thinking was creating excitement.  The success of these initiatives toward a new direction in science, though not adding up to be termed a revolution, was significant in that it created bright young graduates, who would go on to become important psychologists towards the end of the century.

In conclusion, falling short of a revolution in the Kuhnian sense, the birth of cognitive psychology was a cornerstone scientific event in its own right.  Cognitive psychology has thus opened up unchartered areas for scientific inquiry.  But in the absence of clarity and consensus even with the community of psychologists, various theories compete and contradict for legitimacy.  At the moment there are more questions than answers to some of the key questions pertaining to research in this domain. In this context, it is pretentious to claim of any well-articulated paradigmatic shift in psychological discourse.  So, scientific revolution in the Kuhnian sense is not a concrete fact.

References:

Bauer, J. E. (1997). The End Science: Facing the Limits of Knowledge in the Twilight of the Scientific Age. Journal of American Culture (Malden, MA)20(4), 113+.

Bruner, J.S. et al. (1956) A Study of Thinking, John Wiley

Crowther-Heyck, H. (1999). George A. Miller, language, and the computer metaphor of mind. History of Psychology, 2, 37– 64.

O’Donohue, W., Ferguson, K. E., & Naugle, A. E. (2003). The Structure of the Cognitive Revolution: An Examination from the Philosophy of Science.  The Behavior Analyst, 26, 85-110

Miller, G. A. (2003). The Cognitive Revolution: A Historical Perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 141-144.

Neisser, U. (1997)., Cognitive psychology. New York, NY: Meredith.

Sperry, R. W. (1993). The Impact and Promise of the Cognitive Revolution. American Psychologist, 48, 878-885.

Watrin, J. P., & Darwich, R. (2012). On behaviourism in the Cognitive Revolution: Myth and Reactions. Review of General Psychology, 16, 269.

White, K. G., McCarthy, D., & Fantino, E. (1999). Cognition and behaviour analysis. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 52, 197–198.

Exit mobile version